Simultaneous Auctions for Complementary Goods Wiroy Shin February 10, 2015 Abstract This paper studies an environment of simultaneous and separate first-price auctions for complementary goods. Agents observe private values of each good before making bids, and the complementarity between goods is explicitly incorporated in their utility. We show that a monotone pure-strategy Bayesian Nash equilibrium exists in this environment. Keywords : simultaneous auctions, multiple-object auctions, first-price auction, private value auctions, equilibrium existence, monotone pure-strategies. JEL Classification : D44, C72 ∗ Department of Economics, The Pennsylvania State University, University Park, PA, 16802, USA. † E-mail address: wus130@psu.edu ‡ I thank to Edward J. Green for his guidance and support throughout this project. I am also grateful for the comments of James Jordan, Leslie Marx, Ed Coulson, Paul Grieco, and seminar participants at Penn State and the 25th International Conference on Game Theory at Stony Brook University. I gratefully acknowledge the Human Capital Foundation, (http://www.hcfoundation.ru/en/) and particularly Andrey P. Vavilov, for research support through the Center for the Study of Auctions, Procurements, and Competition Policy (CAPCP, http://capcp.psu.edu/) at the Pennsylvania State University. All errors are mine. ♯ An earlier version of this paper had been posted on arXiv.org (http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.2641) in December 2013 and had been presented at the 25th International Conference on Game Theory in July 2014. Independently, Gentry et al. (2014), a working paper in simultaneous first-price auctions, was posted on the authors’ websites in October 2014. 1 1 Introduction This paper studies an environment of simultaneous and separate multiple first-price auctions for complementary goods. Agents observe private values of each good before making bids, and the complementarity between goods is explicitly incorporated in their utility. We show that a monotone pure-strategy Bayesian Nash equilibrium exists in this environment. This model, in which the auction mechanism has an exogenous (albeit widely used) form and in which sellers do not interact strategically with one another, is intended to provide a tractable framework for applied research focusing on competition among buyers. Each buyer is trying to acquire a portfolio of objects that must be purchased by auction from several unrelated sellers. EBay’s various sealed-bid auctions under same collectibles category which are run by different sellers with similar closing time can be an example of this environment. Also, less explicit, but equally compelling, auctions for acquisition of firms manufacturing a final good and an intermediate good input can be another example. Here, a buyer intends to create a vertically integrated firm and the two acquired firms can be viewed as complements when they are merged. There are several branches of existing auction research that are similar to, but distinct from, what is being done here. Let us comment briefly on those contributions, and on how the present research is distinguished from them. A literature on multi-unit auctions, including Bresky (1999), McAdams (2003), and Reny (2011) studies sale of multiple identical goods in an auction with specific pricing rules. As modeled, multiple identical objects resemble substitutable distinct objects rather than complementary ones modeled here. Package auctions(see Bernheim and Whinston (1986) and Ausubel and Milgrom (2002)) model multiple goods without assuming substitutability only. They suppose that an explicit bid can be offered for a package of objects, which is not possible when various objects are auctioned by distinct and unrelated sellers. There are a few prior research contributions on simultaneous auctions, including Krishna and Rosenthal (1996) and Bikhchandani (1999). They either assume a single parameter for private values of the multiple objects or complete information on bidders’ valuations. However, such parameterization is too rigid to model heterogeneity of bidders’ preferences on each item and complementarity. In this paper, we relax those restrictions so that the environment in which each bidder receives private signals for each heterogeneous object is permitted. We follow McAdams (2003) to prove the existence of a monotone pure-strategy Bayesian Nash equilibrium. Along with basic assumptions on the Bayesian game (Assumption13, McAdams (2003)), single crossing differences and quasisupermodularity are required 2 in his paper.1 The remainder of this paper is as follows. In the next section, we present a model of simultaneous first-price auctions for complementary goods in detail with two objects and two agents, and propose a theorem for the existence of a monotone pure-strategy Bayesian Nash equilibrium. Section 3 extends the section 2’s results to multiple (more than two) objects and multiple bidders cases, and section 4 discusses an extension of the study to a continuum bid space setting. Additionally, the appendix provides an example of the model with several subjects that are worthwhile to be investigated in future research on simultaneous auctions. 2 Simultaneous first-price auctions for complementary goods In this section, we define simultaneous first-price auctions for complementary goods with two non-identical objects and two bidders. At the end of the section, we propose a theorem for the existence of a monotone pure-strategy Bayesian Nash equilibrium. 2.1 Environment Bidder i ∈ {1, 2}, i ̸= j ; i’s opponent is denoted by j. Object k ∈ {1, 2}, Values of objects(or bidder’s type) are represented by vector xi = (xi1 , xi2 ). ∀xik ∈ [0, 1] = X, and the vector xi is distributed by F (·) on the support X 2 . Let f (·) be a density function of the cumulative distribution function F (·), and let F (·) be atomless and common knowledge among bidders. Bid bi = (bi1 , bi2 ) ∈ {0, n1 , n2 , ..., ū} × {0, n1 , n2 , ..., ū} = A2 , where n ∈ Z+ and ū ∈ R+ . Each bidder i chooses bids bi1 and bi2 simultaneously from a two dimensional bid space A2 . A2 is a finite subset of R2 . Therefore, A2 , the action space of this game is a Euclidean lattice with a coordinatewise partial order. Utility Bidder i has a quasilinear ex-post utility Ui (bi , bj , xi ). w(xi1 , xi2 ) − (bi1 + bi2 ) if bi1 > bj1 and bi2 > bj2 , where i ̸= j u(x ) − b if bi1 > bj1 and bi2 < bj2 i1 i1 Ui (bi , bj , xi ) = (1) u(xi2 ) − bi2 if bi1 < bj1 and bi2 > bj2 0 otherwise. 1 Theorem 1, McAdams (2003) 3 Note that when ties occur, the object is allocated randomly to one of the two bidders with probability 12 . The ex-post utility Ui can be interpreted as follows. First, an agent realizes his utility from winning objects through a function u : R → R when he wins a single item(e.g. identity function), and w : R2 → R when he wins both items. w(xi1 , xi2 ) transforms the independent values of goods to utility that counts a synergy effect between two objects(e.g. w(xi1 , xi2 ) = xi1 + xi2 + α, where α > 0). And then, the bidding values for the winning objects are subtracted from u(·) or w(·, ·). Additional assumptions on u(·) and w(·, ·) are listed below. Let ≥ be a coordinatewise partial order on the values of objects and bids. For example, when xi , yi ∈ R2 , [xi ≥ yi ⇔ (xi1 ≥ yi1 ) and (xi2 ≥ yi2 )]. (A1) u(·) and w(·, ·) are weakly increasing in their arguments. (A2) Let λ be the complementary value from winning both goods. λ(xi1 , xi2 ) = w(xi1 , xi2 ) − [u(xi1 ) + u(xi2 )] ≥ 0. ; This assumption implies that regardless of the values of objects, agents realize that utility from winning both objects is greater than or equal to sum of utilities of each good. (e.g. Goods are complementary, Acquiring all bike shops in New York City yields monopolistic positioning benefit in the business) (A3)[xi ≥ yi ⇒ λ(xi ) ≥ λ(yi )]. That is, the complementary value λ is weakly increasing in xi = (xi1 , xi2 ). In summary, bidders expect extra synergy by obtaining both items, and the value of synergy is weakly increasing with the values of obtained goods. In addition, since it is reasonable not to bid more than the maximum of utility that an agent can earn, we assign w(1, 1) to the maximum bid on one good, ū. 2.2 Monotone pure-strategy Bayesian Nash equilibrium A pure-strategy for bidder i is a function si : X 2 → A, and it is monotone if x′i ≥ xi implies si (x′i ) ≥ si (xi ), for all x′i , xi ∈ X 2 . Let Si be a set of monotone pure strategies of i. Based on the environment in section 2.1, bidder i’s expected utility is written as follows. Let µsj be an opponent’s bids distribution constructed by the opponent’s purestrategy sj (xj ) and the type distribution F (xj ). Define three probabilities in terms of s s winning cases. P1 j (bi ) and P2 j (bi ) denote probabilities for winning object 1 only and 4 s object 2 only, respectively, when the opponent plays sj . P3 j (bi ) indicates a probability that bidder i wins both objects with bi . 1 s P1 j (bi ) = µsj ([0, bi1 ) × (bi2 , ū]) + µsj ([0, bi1 ) × [bi2 , bi2 ]) 2 1 sj 1 + µ ([bi1 , bi1 ] × (bi2 , ū]) + µsj ([bi1 , bi1 ] × [bi2 , bi2 ]); 2 2 4 1 sj sj sj P2 (bi ) = µ ((bi1 , ū] × [0, bi2 )) + µ ([bi1 , bi1 ] × [0, bi2 )) 2 1 1 sj + µ ((bi1 , ū] × [bi2 , bi2 ]) + µsj ([bi1 , bi1 ] × [bi2 , bi2 ]); 2 4 1 sj sj sj P3 (bi ) = µ ([0, bi1 ) × [0, bi2 )) + µ ([bi1 , bi1 ] × [0, bi2 )) 2 1 sj 1 + µ ([0, bi1 ) × [bi2 , bi2 ]) + µsj ([bi1 , bi1 ] × [bi2 , bi2 ]). 2 4 (2) Then, if an agent with type xi bids bi , the bidder i’s expected utility is s s s Vi (bi , xi , sj ) = P3 j (bi )[w(xi1 , xi2 )−(bi1 +bi2 )]+P1 j (bi )[u(xi1 )−bi1 ]+P2 j (bi )[u(xi2 )−bi2 ]. (3) To make proofs tractable in section 3, we modify the representation of the expected s s s utility. First, we define Q1j , Q2j and Q3j as follows. 1 s Q1j (bi1 ) = µsj ([0, bi1 ) × [0, ū]) + µsj ([bi1 , bi1 ] × [0, ū]); 2 1 sj Q2 (bi2 ) = µsj ([0, ū] × [0, bi2 )) + µsj ([0, ū] × [bi2 , bi2 ]); 2 s s Q3j (bi1 , bi2 ) = P3 j (bi ). (4) s Q1j (bi1 ) denotes a probability that bidder i with a bid bi1 wins the object 1 regardless s of i’s acquiring object 2. Similarly, Q2j (bi2 ) describes a probability that bidder i with a s bid bi2 wins the object 2. Note that Q1j only depends on bi1 and is weakly increasing s s in bi1 , and Q2j only depends on bi2 and is weakly increasing in bi2 . Q3j , the probability of winning both objects is weakly increasing in (bi1 , bi2 ) with the coordinatewise partial order. s s s The redefined winning probability functions (4) imply [P3 j (bi ) = Q3j (bi ), P1 j (bi ) = s s s s s Q1j (bi1 ) − Q3j (bi ), P2 j (bi ) = Q2j (bi2 ) − Q3j (bi )]. Substituting these to the expected utility function (3), we have µsj ([0, bi1 )×(bi2 , ū]) = probability(0 ≤ bj1 < bi1 , bi2 < bj2 ≤ ū). The terms with coefficients 12 and count the probabilities of events that ties occur for one and both of the two objects, respectively. 2 5 1 4 s s Vi (bi , xi , sj ) = Q1j (bi1 )[u(xi1 ) − bi1 ] + Q2j (bi2 )[u(xi2 ) − bi2 ] s +Q3j (bi1 , bi2 )[w(xi1 , xi2 ) − (bi1 + bi2 ) − (u(xi1 ) − bi1 ) − (u(xi2 ) − bi2 )] s s = Q1j (bi1 )[u(xi1 ) − bi1 ] + Q2j (bi2 )[u(xi2 ) − bi2 ] = s +Q3j (bi1 , bi2 )[w(xi1 , xi2 ) − u(xi1 ) − u(xi2 )] s s Q1j (bi1 )[u(xi1 ) − bi1 ] + Q2j (bi2 )[u(xi2 ) − bi2 ] (5) s + Q3j (bi1 , bi2 )λ(xi ). Under the auction environment in section 2.1, (s1 , s2 ) ∈ S1 × S2 is a monotone purestrategy Bayesian Nash equilibrium, if for every bidder i ∈ {1, 2} and every xi ∈ X 2 , Vi (si (xi ), xi , sj ) ≥ Vi (bi , xi , sj ) (6) for all bi ∈ A2 . Theorem 1. A monotone pure-strategy Bayesian Nash equilibrium exists in simultaneous first-price auctions for complementary goods, which are specified in section 2.1. 2.3 Proof of Theorem 1 Under the simultaneous auctions environment in section 2.1, we have a finite common actions set A2 and an atomless cumulative distribution function for object values with a two-dimensional compact support. Therefore, by employing the coordinate partial order and usual Euclidean topology and measure, Assumption 1-2 in McAdams (2003) are satisfied. The assumption 3 is also satisfied by the fact that the ex-post utility Ui defined in (1) is bounded and jointly measurable in bi ∈ A2 for every xi ∈ X 2 . Therefore, by the theorem 1 in McAdams (2003), if the interim utility Vi (bi , xi , sj ) satisfies single crossing differences and quasisupermodularity for all monotone pure-strategies of the opponent sj , Theorem 1 is proved. Lemma 1 and Lemma 2 in the following sections show that the two conditions are satisfied for all pure-strategies of the opponent in the simultaneous auctions environment of section 2.1. 2.3.1 Single crossing differences of Vi (bi , xi , sj ) Definition 1. Vi (bi , xi , sj ) satisfies single crossing differences, if for all pure-strategies sj of the opponent, for all b′i ≥ bi , and for all x′i ≥ xi , Vi (b′i , xi , sj ) ≥ (>)Vi (bi , xi , sj ) implies Vi (b′i , x′i , sj ) ≥ (>)Vi (bi , x′i , sj ). (7) (Weak inequality implies weak inequality, and strict inequality implies strict inequality.) 6 Let b′i = (bhi1 , bhi2 ), bi = (bli1 , bli2 ), x′i = (xhi1 , xhi2 ) and xi = (xli1 , xli2 ), where bhik ≥ blik and xhik ≥ xlik for k ∈ {1, 2}. Lemma 1. With bi , b′i , xi and x′i , (7) holds. That is, Vi (bhi1 , bhi2 , xi , sj ) − Vi (bli1 , bli2 , xi , sj ) ≥ (>)0 (8) Vi (bhi1 , bhi2 , x′i , sj ) − Vi (bli1 , bli2 , x′i , sj ) ≥ (>)0. (9) implies Proof. By (5), (8) gives s s Q1j (bhi1 )[u(xli1 ) − bhi1 ] + Q2j (bhi2 )[u(xli2 ) − bhi2 ] s +Q3j (bhi1 , bhi2 )[w(xli1 , xli2 ) − u(xli1 ) − u(xli2 )] ≥ (>) s (10) s Q1j (bli1 )[u(xli1 ) − bli1 ] + Q2j (bli2 )[u(xli2 ) − bli2 ] s +Q3j (bli1 , bli2 )[w(xli1 , xli2 ) − u(xli1 ) − u(xli2 )] s ⇔ s [Q3j (bhi1 , bhi2 ) − Q3j (bli1 , bli2 )]λ(xi ) s ≥ (>) s [Q1j (bli1 )[u(xli1 ) − bli1 ] − Q1j (bhi1 )[u(xli1 ) − bhi1 ]] s (11) s +[Q2j (bli2 )[u(xli2 ) − bli2 ] − Q2j (bhi2 )[u(xli2 ) − bhi2 ]] We want to show that (11) gives (9). Rewriting (9), [Q3j (bhi1 , bhi2 ) − Q3j (bli1 , bli2 )]λ(x′i ) s s s ≥ (>) s [Q1j (bli1 )[u(xhi1 ) − bli1 ] − Q1j (bhi1 )[u(xhi1 ) − bhi1 ]] s +[Q2j (bli2 )[u(xhi2 ) − bli2 ] − s Q2j (bhi2 )[u(xhi2 ) − (12) bhi2 ]] To prove the lemma, it is sufficient to show that [(LHS(12) ≥ LHS(11)) and (RHS(11) ≥ RHS(12))]. LHS(12) − LHS(11) = [Q3j (bhi1 , bhi2 ) − Q3j (bli1 , bli2 )] · [λ(x′i ) − λ(xi )] ≥ 0. s s (13) s The inequality comes from the fact that both terms are nonnegative. Q3j is weakly increasing in its argument. Also, λ(xi ) is weakly increasing in xi by (A3) of section 2.1, and x′i ≥ xi . 3 3 If bidders are risk averse, the argument in the proof of Lemma 1 is not applicable. For example, suppose u(xik ) = xik and λ(xi ) = α > 0. Let r(·) : R+ → R+ be a concave function, where r′ > 0 and s r′′ < 0. Then, the expected utility function can be written as Vi (bi , xi , sj ) = Q1j (bi1 )[r(xi1 − bi1 )] + 7 s s RHS(11) − RHS(12) = Q1j (bli1 )[u(xli1 ) − u(xhi1 )] − Q1j (bhi1 )[u(xli1 ) − u(xhi1 )] s s +Q2j (bli2 )[u(xli2 ) − u(xhi2 )] − Q2j (bhi2 )[u(xli2 ) − u(xhi2 )] s s = [Q1j (bli1 ) − Q1j (bhi1 )][u(xli1 ) − u(xhi1 )] s +[Q2j (bli2 ) − s Q2j (bhi2 )][u(xli2 ) (14) − u(xhi2 )] ≥ 0 s s The inequality comes from the fact that Q1j , Q2j and u are weakly increasing in their arguments. ♦ By Lemma 1, Vi (bi , xi , sj ) satisfies single crossing differences. 2.3.2 Quasisupermodularity of Vi (bi , xi , sj ) Definition 2. Vi (bi , xi , sj ) is quasisupermodular if for all pure strategies sj of the opponent, all bi , b′i ∈ A, and every xi ∈ X 2 , Vi (bi , xi , sj ) ≥ (>)Vi (bi ∧ b′i , xi , sj ) implies Vi (bi ∨ b′i , xi , sj ) ≥ (>)Vi (b′i , xi , sj ). (15) If b′i ≥ bi , where ≥ is a coordinatewise partial order, (15) holds trivially. Therefore, we focus on a case [(bi1 > b′i1 ) and (bi2 < b′i2 )]4 . Denote bi = (bhi1 , bli2 ) and b′i = (bli1 , bhi2 ), where bhik > blik for k ∈ {1, 2}. Substitute bi , b′i , to (15). That is, Vi (bhi1 , bli2 , xi , sj ) − Vi (bli1 , bli2 , xi , sj ) ≥ (>)0 (16) Vi (bhi1 , bhi2 , xi , sj ) − Vi (bli1 , bhi2 , xi , sj ) ≥ (>)0. (17) implies (16) gives s s Q1j (bhi1 )[u(xi1 ) − bhi1 ] + Q2j (bli2 )[u(xi2 ) − bli2 ] s +Q3j (bhi1 , bli2 )[w(xi1 , xi2 ) − u(xi1 ) − u(xi2 )] ≥ (>) s s Q1j (bli1 )[u(xi1 ) − bli1 ] + Q2j (bli2 )[u(xi2 ) − bli2 ] (18) s +Q3j (bli1 , bli2 )[w(xi1 , xi2 ) − u(xi1 ) − u(xi2 )] s s Q2j (bi2 )[r(xi2 − bi2 )] + Q3j (bi1 , bi2 )[r(α + xi1 − bi1 + xi2 − bi2 ) − r(xi1 − bi1 ) − r(xi2 − bi2 )]. Following the same procedure from (8) to(14), inequality between LHS(12) and LHS(11) is undetermined in the risk averse utility setting , while (14) still holds. 4 A proof for weak quasisupermodularity of this case similarly applies to the opposite case [(bi1 < ′ bi1 ) and (bi2 > b′i2 )]. 8 s s s s ⇔ Q1j (bhi1 )[u(xi1 ) − bhi1 ] − Q1j (bli1 )[u(xi1 ) − bli1 ] ≥ (>)[Q3j (bli1 , bli2 ) − Q3j (bhi1 , bli2 )]λ(xi ). (19) Rewriting (17), s s s s Q1j (bhi1 )[u(xi1 )−bhi1 ]−Q1j (bli1 )[u(xi1 )−bli1 ] ≥ (>)[Q3j (bli1 , bhi2 )−Q3j (bhi1 , bhi2 )]λ(xi ). (20) Since LHS of (19) and (20) are identical, a sufficient condition for quasisupermodularity is [RHS (19) ≥ RHS (20)]. RHS(19) − RHS(20) = λ(xi ) · (21) s s s s [[Q3j (bhi1 , bhi2 ) − Q3j (bhi1 , bli2 )] − [Q3j (bli1 , bhi2 ) − Q3j (bli1 , bli2 )]]. With the assumption(A2) λ(xi ) ≥ 0 in section 2.1 , for quasisupermodularity, it is sufficient to show that the next term of λ(xi ) in (21) is positive. That is, we want to show that s s s s [Q3j (bhi1 , bhi2 ) − Q3j (bhi1 , bli2 )] − [Q3j (bli1 , bhi2 ) − Q3j (bli1 , bli2 )] ≥ 0. (22) Lemma 2. Recall X 2 = [0, 1] × [0, 1] and A2 = {0, n1 , n2 , ..., ū} × {0, n1 , n2 , ..., ū}, n ∈ Z+ in the auction environment of section 2.1. In this environment, the inequality (22), which is a sufficient condition of quasisupermodularity, holds for all pure-strategies of the opponent. Proof. Let xj ∈ X × X be object values of the opponent j and f (xj ) = probability(xj ). First, we define qi (bi , bj ), i’s ex-post winning probability function for two objects, as follows. 1 if bi > bj 1/2 if [(b > b ) and (b = b )] or [(b = b ]) and (b > b )] i1 j1 i2 j2 i1 j1 i2 j2 qi (bi , bj ) = 1/4 if bi = bj 0 otherwise. (23) Suppose that the opponent j plays an arbitrary pure-strategy sj (xj ) = (sj1 (xj ), sj2 (xj )). 9 s Then, given sj , the bidder i’s interim probability for winning both objects Q3j (bi ) is s Q3j (bi ) ∫ = xj ∈X 2 f (xj ) · qi (bi , sj (xj )) dxj . (24) As a result, the LHS of (22) can be expressed as follows. s s s s [Q3j (bhi1 , bhi2 ) − Q3j (bhi1 , bli2 )] − [Q3j (bli1 , bhi2 ) − Q3j (bli1 , bli2 )] ∫ = f (xj )[{qi (bhi1 , bhi2 , sj (xj )) − qi (bhi1 , bli2 , sj (xj ))} xj ∈X 2 ∫ = xj ∈X 2 −{qi (bli1 , bhi2 , sj (xj )) − qi (bli1 , bli2 , sj (xj ))}] dxj f (xj )[H(bhi1 , bli2 , bhi2 , sj (xj )) − D(bli1 , bli2 , bhi2 , sj (xj ))] dxj , (25) where H(bhi1 , bli2 , bhi2 , sj (xj )) = qi (bhi1 , bhi2 , sj (xj )) − qi (bhi1 , bli2 , sj (xj )) and D(bli1 , bli2 , bhi2 , sj (xj )) = qi (bli1 , bhi2 , sj (xj )) − qi (bli1 , bli2 , sj (xj )). Note that when the agent i increases the second object’s bid from bli2 to bhi2 , H represents the increase in the ex-post winning probability for both objects, while bidding high for the first object. D describes the same effect, when i bids low for the first object. For the proof, we need to show that the second term of the integral in (25) is always positive. That is, ∀sj (xj ), ∀b⃗i ∈ {(bl , bl , bh , bh )| bh > bl , k ∈ {1, 2}}, i1 i2 i1 i2 ik ik H(bhi1 , bli2 , bhi2 , sj (xj )) − D(bli1 , bli2 , bhi2 , sj (xj )) ≥ 0 (26) . Let βj = (βj1 , βj2 ) be an arbitrary two-dimensional bid vector generated by sj (xj ) and xj ∈ X 2 . Table 1 shows values of H(·) − D(·) for every 25 cases determined by the values of (blik , bhik , βjk )k∈{1,2} . In the table, every cell is composed of a difference between two brackets. The first bracket corresponds to the value of H(·), and the second bracket corresponds to the value of D(·). For instance, a cell at the 3rd row and the 3rd column in the table contains [ 14 − 0] − [0 − 0]. In this cell, the first bracket [ 41 − 0] corresponds to H(bhi1 , bli2 , bhi2 , sj (xj )) = qi (bhi1 , bhi2 , sj (xj )) − qi (bhi1 , bli2 , sj (xj )), when [bli1 < bhi1 = βj1 ] and [bli2 < bhi2 = βj2 ]. From the table, we observe that every value of cells is positive. Therefore, with f (xj ) ≥ 0, the value of the integral in (25) is positive and the inequality (22) holds. ♦ By Lemma 2, the interim utility Vi (bi , xi , sj ) is quasisupermodular. Together with Lemma 1, this completes the proof of Theorem 1. 10 Table 1: H(bhi1 , bli2 , bhi2 , sj (xj )) − D(bli1 , bli2 , bhi2 , sj (xj )) H −D bli2 < bhi2 < βj2 bli2 < bhi2 = βj2 bli2 < βj2 < bhi2 bli2 = βj2 < bhi2 βj2 < bli2 < bhi2 bli1 < bhi1 < βj1 [0 − 0] − [0 − 0] [0 − 0] − [0 − 0] [0 − 0] − [0 − 0] [0 − 0] − [0 − 0] [0 − 0] − [0 − 0] bli1 < bhi1 = βj1 [0 − 0] − [0 − 0] [ 14 − 0] − [0 − 0] [ 12 − 0] − [0 − 0] [ 12 − 41 ] − [0 − 0] [ 21 − 21 ] − [0 − 0] bli1 < βj1 < bhi1 [0 − 0] − [0 − 0] [ 12 − 0] − [0 − 0] [1 − 0] − [0 − 0] [1 − 21 ] − [0 − 0] [1 − 1] − [0 − 0] bli1 = βj1 < bhi1 [0 − 0] − [0 − 0] [ 12 − 0] − [ 14 − 0] [1 − 0] − [ 21 − 0] [1 − 21 ] − [ 21 − 14 ] [1 − 1] − [ 21 − 12 ] βj1 < bli1 < bhi1 [0 − 0] − [0 − 0] [ 12 − 0] − [ 12 − 0] [1 − 0] − [1 − 0] [1 − 12 ] − [1 − 21 ] [1 − 1] − [1 − 1] 3 Extension to multiple objects and agents environment In this section, we show that the arguments in section 2 can be extended to multiple objects and multiple agents cases. Assumptions on bid and type spaces are same as section 2.1. That is, for each k, bik ∈ A, xik ∈ X, and xi ∼ F (·), where F (·) is atomless. Therefore, for the extension, it is sufficient to argue whether the proofs of Lemma 1 and Lemma 2 are maintained in multiple objects and multiple agents case. In the following sections, we discuss the extendability under two objects and multiple agents setting; multiple objects and two agents setting; and multiple objects and multiple agents setting. 3.1 Two objects and multiple agents case Suppose k ∈ {1, 2} and i ∈ {1, 2, ..., I}. Then, the winning probabilities defined in (4) change reflecting first-order statistics of the opponents’ bids on the two objects. Define yk as the bidder i’s opponents’ highest bid on the object k. That is, yk = maxi′ ̸=i bi′ k . Let µs−i be distributions of y1 and y2 constructed by the opponents’ pure-strategies s−i and the type distribution F . Also, let τk (bik , j) be a probability that there are j number of bi′ k s.t. bi′ k = yk when bidder i bids bik . Similarly, τ3 (bi1 , bi2 , j, m) is defined for a probability that j and m ties occur for the object 1 and 2 respectively. Then, the winning probabilities in (4) are modified as follows. 11 s I−1 ∑ s I−1 ∑ Q1−i (bi1 ) = µs−i ([0, bi1 ) × [0, ū]) + µs−i ([bi1 , bi1 ] × [0, ū]) · j=1 Q2−i (bi2 ) = µs−i ([0, ū] × [0, bi2 )) + µs−i ([0, ū] × [bi2 , bi2 ]) · j=1 s Q3−i (bi1 , bi2 ) = µs−i ([0, bi1 ) × [0, bi2 )) + µs−i ([bi1 , bi1 ] × [0, bi2 )) · 1 · τ1 (bi1 , j); j+1 1 · τ2 (bi2 , j); j+1 I−1 ∑ j=1 +µs−i ([0, bi1 ) × [bi2 , bi2 ]) · I−1 ∑ j=1 +µs−i ([bi1 , bi1 ] × [bi2 , bi2 ]) · 1 · τ2 (bi2 , j) j+1 I−1 ∑ I−1 ∑ j=1 m=1 s s 1 · τ1 (bi1(27) , j) j+1 1 1 · · τ3 (bi1 , bi2 , j, m). j+1 m+1 s Given s−i , Q1−i , Q2−i and Q3−i are weakly increasing in their arguments. Therefore, the proof for Lemma 1 (Single crossing differences) is valid under the multiple agents assumption. The proof for Lemma 2 (Quasisupermodularity) is also maintained by replacing values of qi in Table 1. For the change of the table, instead of βj1 and βj2 , cases are divided by inequalities between (y1 , y2 ) and (bli1 , bli2 , bhi1 , bhi2 ). Under the multiple agents assumption, qi in (23) is newly defined as follows. 1 1 qi (bi , b−i ) = j+1 1 j+1 0 In (28), 1 j+1 if bik > yk , ∀k ∈ {1, 2}; if bi(3−k) > y(3−k) , and the number of ties for the object k is j, ∀k ∈ {1, 2}; · 1 m+1 if j and m ties occur for the object 1 and 2; otherwise. and 1 m+1 are bounded above by 21 . Calculating H(·) and D(·) based on the new qi in (28), every value in Table 1 is positive. Therefore, Lemma 2 also holds under the two objects and multiple agents setting. 3.2 Multiple objects and two agents case Suppose k ∈ {1, 2, ..., N } = K and i ∈ {1, 2}. We assume that bidder i obtains the complementarity value by winning a whole set K.5 Let Γ be an arbitrary proper subset of K. Then, the ex-post utility defined in (1) is modified as follows. 5 As the number of objects (auctions) increases, the number of ways to assume complementarity between objects also exponentially increases. In the extension, we assume that the agents obtain the complementary value when they acquire all items. 12 (28) ∑ w(xi ) − N k=1 (bik ) if bik > bjk , ∀k ∈ K ∑ Ui (bi , bj , xi ) = if bik > bjk , ∀k ∈ Γ and bi2 < bj2 , ∀k ∈ K\Γ(29) k∈Γ u(xik ) − bik 0 otherwise. Note that when ties occur, the object is allocated randomly to one of the two bidders with probability 12 . The assumptions on u(·) and w(·), (A1), (A2), and (A3) in section ∑ 2.1, are maintained for this extension with λ(xi ) = w(xi ) − k∈K u(xik ). The winning s s probability for each k ∈ K and a whole set K are denoted by Qkj (bik ) and QKj (bi ). Then, the expected utility function can be defined as follows. Vi (bi , xi , sj ) = N ∑ s s Qkj (bik ) · [u(xik ) − bik ] + QKj (bi ) · λ(xik ) (30) k=1 The conditions for single crossing differences (31) and (32), which are modified versions of (13) and (14), hold for the multiple goods case as below with the monotonicity s s assumptions of Qkj , QKj , u, and λ. s [QKj (bhi ) − QK (bli )] · [λ(xhi ) − λ(xli )] ≥ 0. N ∑ s s [Qkj (blik ) − Qkj (bhik )] · [u(xlik ) − u(xhik )] ≥ 0. (31) (32) k=1 To extend the quasisupermodularity proof in Lemma 2, let bi , b′i be bidder i’s two arbitrary N -dimensional bids. Define J to be a subset of K, where ∀k ∈ J, bik ≥ b′ik and let J ′ = K\J. Then, ∀k ∈ J ′ ⊂ K, bik < b′ik . Denote bi = (bhJ , blJ ′ ) and b′i = (bliJ , bhiJ ′ ), where for ∀k ∈ K, bhik ≥ blik , and [bhiJ = {bhik }k∈J ; bliJ ′ = {blik }k∈J ′ ; bliJ = {blik }k∈J ; and bhiJ ′ = {bhik }k∈J ′ ]. Let y be the opponent’s bids for N objects generated by arbitrary sj and xj . Given (bhik , blik )k∈K , the opponent’s bids y can be categorized into four cases. 1. Let y ∈ ϕ1 ⊂ AN . Then, ∃k ∈ K, yk > bhik . 2. Let y ∈ ϕ2 ⊂ AN \ϕ1 . Then, ∃k s.t. yk = bhik . 3. Let y ∈ ϕ3 ⊂ AN \(ϕ1 ∪ ϕ2 ). Then, ∃k s.t. yk > blik . 4. Let y ∈ ϕ4 ⊂ AN \(ϕ1 ∪ ϕ2 ∪ ϕ3 ). Then, ∀k, yk ≤ blik . To satisfy quasisupermodularity, we need to show that the inequality (26) holds for all of the four cases. That is, for all bi , b′i , y ∈ AN , 13 H(bhiJ , bliJ ′ , bhiJ ′ , y) − D((bliJ , bhiJ ′ , bhiJ , y) (33) = [qi (bhiJ , bhiJ ′ , y) − qi (bhiJ , bliJ ′ , y)] − [qi (bliJ , bhiJ ′ , y) − qi (bliJ , bliJ ′ , y)] ≥ 0. The following part shows that ∀y ∈ AN , the inequality (33) holds. 1. Let y ∈ ϕ1 . In this case, every qi (·) = 0. Therefore, LHS (33) = [0 − 0] − [0 − 0] = 0 2. Let y ∈ ϕ2 . 2(a). Suppose that for some k ∈ J, [yk = bhik > blik ]. Then, D((bliJ , bhiJ ′ , bhiJ , y) = [qi (bliJ , bhiJ ′ , y) − qi (bliJ , bliJ ′ , y)] = 0. H(bhiJ , bliJ ′ , bhiJ ′ , y) ≥ 0 as qi (·) is increas- ing in bidder i’s bids. Therefore, LHS (33) ≥ 0. If such k ∈ J ′ , then qi (bhiJ , bliJ ′ , y) = 0 and LHS (33) ≥ 0. 2(b) Suppose that 2(a) is not the case. Then, there are some k ∈ J ∪ J ′ s.t. [yk = bhik = blik ]. Let j be a set of objects k ∈ J s.t. [yk = bhik = blik ]. Similarly, let j ′ be a subset of objects k ∈ J ′ s.t. [yk = bhik = blik ]. If |j| = |J| and 1 |j ′ | = |J ′ |, then LHS (33) =[ 2( |j|+|j ′ |) − 1 1 ] − [ 2( |j|+|j ′ |) 2( |j|+|j ′ |) − 1 ] 2( |j|+|j ′ |) = 0. Assume |j| < |J| or |j ′ | < |J ′ |. Suppose that ∃yk s.t. k ∈ J\j = j c and bhik > yk > blik . Then, D(·) = 0. Therefore, LHS (33) ≥ 0. Suppose that such k ∈ J ′ \j ′ = j ′c , then qi (bhiJ , bliJ ′ , y) = 0 and LHS (33) ≥ 0. Now, assume ∀k ∈ j c or j ′c , bhik > blik ≥ yk . Let η be a subset of j c s.t. ∀k ∈ η, blik = yk , and let η ′ be a subset of j ′c s.t. ∀k ∈ η ′ , blik = yk . Then, for all |η|, |η ′ | 1 s.t. 0 ≤ |η| ≤ |j c | and 0 ≤ |η ′ | ≤ |j ′c |, LHS (33) = [ 2|j|+|j ′| − −[ 2|j|+|η| · 1 1 2|j ′| − 1 2|j|+|η| · 1 2|j ′ |+|η ′ | ] ≥ 0. 1 2|j| · 1 2|j ′ |+|η ′ | ] 3. Let y ∈ ϕ3 . Suppose that for some k ∈ J, yk > blik . Then, qi (bliJ , bhiJ ′ , y) = 0. Therefore, qi (bliJ , bhiJ ′ , y) − qi (bliJ , bliJ ′ , y) = 0. Since [qi (bhiJ , bhiJ ′ , y) − qi (bhiJ , bliJ ′ , y)] ≥ 0, LHS (33) ≥ 0. If such k ∈ J ′ , qi (bhiJ , bliJ ′ , y) = 0 and LHS (33) ≥ 0. 4. Let y ∈ ϕ4 . Suppose that ∀k ∈ K, yk < blik . Then, LHS (33) = [1 − 1] − [1 − 1] = 0. Otherwise, let j be a subset of J s.t. ∀k ∈ j, yk = blik , and let j ′ be a subset of J ′ s.t. ∀k ∈ j ′ , yk = blik . Then, for all |j|, |j ′ |, s.t. 0 ≤ |j| ≤ |J|, 0 ≤ |j ′ | ≤ |J ′ |, and j + j ′ ≥ 1, LHS (33) = 1 − 1 2|j| − 1 ′ 2|j | + 14 1 2|j| · 1 ′ 2|j | ≥ 0. 3.3 Multiple objects and multiple agents case s s s Qkj and QKj in section 3.2 (multiple objects and two agents case) can be rewritten as Qk−i s s s s and QK−i assuming multiple opponents, similarly to Q1−i (bi1 ), Q2−i (bi2 ), and Q3−i (bi ) in (27). Then, the inequalities (31) and (32) still hold by the monotonicity assumptions s s of Qk−i , QK−i , u, and λ. The argument for quasisupermodularity in section 3.2 is also extendable to the multiple agents case by defining y to be a vector of first-order statistics in the opponents’ bids and adjusting the probabilities of ties. Therefore, a monotone pure-strategy Bayesian Nash equilibrium exists in the simultaneous first-price auctions for complementary goods with N goods and I bidders. 4 Conclusion This paper has shown the existence of a monotone pure-strategy Bayesian Nash equilibrium in simultaneous first-price auctions, where the objects have synergy in bidders’ utility. Under the complementarity assumptions, single crossing differences and quasisupermodularity of interim utility are satisfied, so McAdams (2003)’s existence theorem is applicable to this environment. As future research, it is meaningful to think about the environment in a continuum action space setting. As Athey (2001) argues in the paper, it would support a differential equation approach to verify existence conditions. She provides the extension with a continuum action space by showing ties do not occur in the game. Reny (2011) also presents the extension through a better-reply secure game and a limit of a pure-strategy of ϵ equilibria. Appendix A.1 Example of the two objects and two agents case Consider an environment of simultaneous first-price auctions with two objects and two agents. For each agent i, the private valuation of each good xik is either 0 or 2 with probability 21 , and each bid bik for k ∈ {1, 2} is submitted from A = {0, 1} simultaneously. Thus, there exist four types of xi ∈ {(0, 0), (0, 2), (2, 0), (2, 2)}, and 28 types of pure-strategies. u(xik ) = xik and w(xi1 , xi2 ) = xi1 + xi2 + α, where α = 2. That is, if the bidder i wins both items, complementarity value α = 2 is created. In this environment, there exist five different pure-strategy Bayesian Nash equilibria , which are all monotone. Four equilibria are symmetric (Table 2), and one equilibrium is asymmetric (Table 3). In Table 2(a)-(d) and Table 3, the first three columns present 15 each equilibrium strategy si (xi ). For example, in Table 2(a), the cell (0, 1) corresponds to si (0, 2). The next three columns specify expected utility V , probability of winning both goods Q3 , and expected payment E(pay) of a bidder for each equilibrium. In the result of this example, there are three notable points. First, we can observe over-bidding behavior in equilibrium strategies due to the complementarity. In the equilibrium described in Table 2(b), si (2, 0) = (1, 1). Therefore, under this equilibrium, when bidders’ type is (2, 0), bidders bid 1 for the second object, even though the single valuation for the second object is 0. Such over-bidding is also observed in the equilibrium of Table 2(c), 2(d), and 3(a). Second, the asymmetric equilibrium is consist of an aggressive (high) bidding strategy (Table 3(a)) and an conservative (low) bidding strategy (Table 3(b)). Such equilibrium can be justified in the following way. Given the fact that the opponent plays an conservative bidding without any over-bidding, the bidder i has high chances to win both items and to enjoy the complementary value if he bids aggressively for both goods. Similarly, if the opponent plays an aggressive bidding with over-bidding, the bidder i has low chances to win both items, so bidding based on single good valuation can be rational in such case. Finally, average probability of winning both goods is maximized in a symmetric equilibrium (Table 2(d)) where both players employ an aggressive bidding strategy. Note that utility functions are linear and the utilities are transferable between sellers and bidders. Therefore, a social planner who maximizes the sum of utilities of two agents and two sellers would be interested in increasing a probability that the complementary value is created. Such probability is maximized when both bidders bid aggressively as Q3 = 0.3438 in Table 2(d). 16 Table 2: Symmetric Equilibria (a) xi1 \xi2 0 2 V Q3 E(pay) 0 (0,0) (0,1) 1.25 0.25 0.75 2 (1,0) (1,1) (b) xi1 \xi2 0 2 V Q3 E(pay) 0 (0,0) (0,1) 1.1562 0.3125 0.8438 2 (1,1) (1,1) (c) xi1 \xi2 0 2 V Q3 E(pay) 0 (0,0) (1,1) 1.1562 0.3125 0.8438 2 (1,0) (1,1) (d) xi1 \xi2 0 2 V Q3 E(pay) 0 (0,0) (1,1) 1 0.3438 0.9375 2 (1,1) (1,1) 17 Table 3: Asymmetric equilibrium (a) s1 xi1 \xi2 0 2 V Q3 E(pay) 0 (0,0) (1,1) 1.25 0.4375 1.125 2 (1,1) (1,1) (b) s2 xi1 \xi2 0 2 V Q3 E(pay) 0 (0,0) (0,1) 1 0.1875 0.6250 2 (1,0) (1,1) References Athey, Susan (2001) “Single crossing properties and the existence of pure strategy equilibria in games of incomplete information,” Econometrica, Vol. 69, No. 4, pp. 861–889. Ausubel, Lawrence M and Paul Milgrom (2002) “Ascending auctions with package bidding,” Frontiers of theoretical economics, Vol. 1, No. 1, pp. 1–42. Bernheim, B Douglas and Michael D Whinston (1986) “Menu auctions, resource allocation, and economic influence,” The quarterly journal of economics, Vol. 101, No. 1, pp. 1–31. Bikhchandani, Sushil (1999) “Auctions of heterogeneous objects,” Games and Economic Behavior, Vol. 26, No. 2, pp. 193–220. Bresky, Michal (1999) “Equilibria in multi-unit auctions,” CERGE-EI Working paper series, Prague. Gentry, Matthew, Tatiana Komarova, and Pasquale Schiraldi (2014) “Simultaneous First-Price Auctions with Preferences over Combinations,” http://personal.lse. ac.uk/schirald/GKS_SimultFPA_2014_10_24.pdf. Krishna, Vijay and Robert W Rosenthal (1996) “Simultaneous auctions with synergies,” Games and economic behavior, Vol. 17, No. 1, pp. 1–31. McAdams, David (2003) “Isotone equilibrium in games of incomplete information,” Econometrica, Vol. 71, No. 4, pp. 1191–1214. 18 Reny, Philip J (2011) “On the existence of monotone pure-strategy equilibria in Bayesian games,” Econometrica, Vol. 79, No. 2, pp. 499–553. 19
© Copyright 2025 Paperzz